Expected Utility Theory and
Prospect Theory
April 8, 1999
Why is expected utility the "right"
thing to do?
Not at all clear why one should choose the
option with highest expected utility if youre
only going to play once
Basics of Axiomatic EUT
- Start with a set of raw consequences
{a,b,c,
}. For example: apple, banana, cookie
- Consider choices among all lottery
mixtures of the raw consequences
- Lottery mixture (A,p;B) = "You
get A with prob. p; otherwise you get B"
- Given certain properties (axioms) hold
among your choices between lotteries, then its
as if you choose by picking the lottery with highest
expected utility
Transitivity
If A is preferred to B, and B is preferred
to C, then A is preferred to C
In symbols:
If A >*B, and B >*C, then A>*C
Intuition: Implies a consistent ordering of
the lotteries (and raw consequences too)
Solvability/Continuity
If A >* B >* C, then theres
some probability p between 0 and 1 such that
B ~ (A,p;C)
Can mix best and worst options in a lottery
so that youre indifferent between the lottery and the
middle option
Intuition: can trade-off value and
probability
Independence/Cancellation
If A>*B, then (A,p;C) >* (B,p;C), for
any possible C
Intuition: If you like apples better than
bananas, youll choose any lottery that pays off in
apples over an equivalent lottery that pays off in bananas
Invariance / Compound Lotteries
((A,p;B),q;B) ~ (A,pq;B)
Multi-stage lotteries treated as same as
equivalent single-stage lotteries
Intuition: should follow rules of
probability theory
Representation Theorem
If these axioms hold, then there exists
(mathematically) a utility function u(.), defined for each of
the raw consequences, and choices between lotteries are based
on choosing the one with highest expected utility
Comments
- Utility is extracted from choices
- Utility represents the way value and
probability interact
- Utility need not correspond to
subjective value (but fortunately it does most of the
time)
- No circularity / tautology. Choices
are rational if they obey the axioms.
- Utility provides a common scale for
comparing different outcomes
Who cares? What good is it?
Can be used to predict or guide behavior
Decision analysis
Can test individual axioms, and build
better models of behavior by cutting/pasting/tweaking
different axioms
Subjective expected utility
Descriptive Problems with EUT
Asian disease expected to kill 600 people
- Program A: 200 people will be saved
[72%]
- Program B: 1/3 chance 600 will be
saved, 2/3 chance no one will be saved [28%]
- Program C: 400 people will die [22%]
- Program D: 1/3 chance nobody will die,
2/3 chance 600 people will die [78%]
Descriptive Problems with EUT
- A: sure gain of $240 [82%]
- B: 25% chance to gain $1000; 75% to
gain nothing [18%]
- C: sure loss of $750 [27%]
- D: 75% chance to lose $1000; 25% to
lose nothing [73%]
Prospect theory value function
Three key features
- Evaluate gains and losses relative to
a reference point
- Risk-averse for gains, risk-seeking
for losses
- Loss aversion: losses loom larger than
gains
More problems for EUT
Allais paradox
- A: $1 billion for sure
- B: 10% chance at $2.5 billion, 89%
chance at $1 billion, 1% chance at nothing
- C: 11% chance at $1 billion, 89%
chance at nothing
- D: 10% chance at $2.5 billion, 90%
chance at nothing
More probability effects
- A: sure win of $30
- B: 80% chance at $45
- C: 25% chance at $30
- D: 20% chance at $45
Fourfold pattern of risk attitudes
Prospect theory probability weighting function
Overweight small probabilities
e.g., Lotto, insurance, Dumb &
Dumber
Underweight medium and large probabilities
Relatively flat in the middle
e.g., buying bullets & lottery
tickets, effort put in to increase chance of success
Pseudocertainty, certainty and possibility
effects
Prospect theory summary
Importance of reference points
gains/losses for value
0 and 1 for probability
Diminishing sensitivity away from ref. pts
RA for gains, RS for losses
insensitivity to middle probabilities
Loss aversion
Next
Mental accounting (Thaler)
segregating and integrating gains and
losses
Single and repeated choices (Kahneman &
Lovallo)
isolation errors
|