Expected Utility Theory and Prospect Theory

April 8, 1999

Why is expected utility the "right" thing to do?

Not at all clear why one should choose the option with highest expected utility if you’re only going to play once

Basics of Axiomatic EUT

  • Start with a set of raw consequences {a,b,c,…}. For example: apple, banana, cookie
  • Consider choices among all lottery mixtures of the raw consequences
  • Lottery mixture (A,p;B) = "You get A with prob. p; otherwise you get B"
  • Given certain properties (axioms) hold among your choices between lotteries, then it’s as if you choose by picking the lottery with highest expected utility

Transitivity

If A is preferred to B, and B is preferred to C, then A is preferred to C

In symbols:

If A >*B, and B >*C, then A>*C

Intuition: Implies a consistent ordering of the lotteries (and raw consequences too)

Solvability/Continuity

If A >* B >* C, then there’s some probability p between 0 and 1 such that

B ~ (A,p;C)

Can mix best and worst options in a lottery so that you’re indifferent between the lottery and the middle option

Intuition: can trade-off value and probability

Independence/Cancellation

If A>*B, then (A,p;C) >* (B,p;C), for any possible C

Intuition: If you like apples better than bananas, you’ll choose any lottery that pays off in apples over an equivalent lottery that pays off in bananas

 

Invariance / Compound Lotteries

((A,p;B),q;B) ~ (A,pq;B)

Multi-stage lotteries treated as same as equivalent single-stage lotteries

Intuition: should follow rules of probability theory

Representation Theorem

If these axioms hold, then there exists (mathematically) a utility function u(.), defined for each of the raw consequences, and choices between lotteries are based on choosing the one with highest expected utility

Comments

  • Utility is extracted from choices
  • Utility represents the way value and probability interact
  • Utility need not correspond to subjective value (but fortunately it does most of the time)
  • No circularity / tautology. Choices are rational if they obey the axioms.
  • Utility provides a common scale for comparing different outcomes

Who cares? What good is it?

Can be used to predict or guide behavior

Decision analysis

Can test individual axioms, and build better models of behavior by cutting/pasting/tweaking different axioms

Subjective expected utility

Descriptive Problems with EUT

Asian disease expected to kill 600 people

  • Program A: 200 people will be saved [72%]
  • Program B: 1/3 chance 600 will be saved, 2/3 chance no one will be saved [28%]
  • Program C: 400 people will die [22%]
  • Program D: 1/3 chance nobody will die, 2/3 chance 600 people will die [78%]

Descriptive Problems with EUT

  • A: sure gain of $240 [82%]
  • B: 25% chance to gain $1000; 75% to gain nothing [18%]
  • C: sure loss of $750 [27%]
  • D: 75% chance to lose $1000; 25% to lose nothing [73%]

 

Prospect theory value function

Three key features

  • Evaluate gains and losses relative to a reference point
  • Risk-averse for gains, risk-seeking for losses
  • Loss aversion: losses loom larger than gains

More problems for EUT

Allais paradox

  • A: $1 billion for sure
  • B: 10% chance at $2.5 billion, 89% chance at $1 billion, 1% chance at nothing
  • C: 11% chance at $1 billion, 89% chance at nothing
  • D: 10% chance at $2.5 billion, 90% chance at nothing

More probability effects

  • A: sure win of $30
  • B: 80% chance at $45
  • C: 25% chance at $30
  • D: 20% chance at $45

Fourfold pattern of risk attitudes

Prospect theory probability weighting function

Overweight small probabilities

e.g., Lotto, insurance, Dumb & Dumber

Underweight medium and large probabilities

Relatively flat in the middle

e.g., buying bullets & lottery tickets, effort put in to increase chance of success

Pseudocertainty, certainty and possibility effects

 

Prospect theory summary

Importance of reference points

gains/losses for value

0 and 1 for probability

Diminishing sensitivity away from ref. pts

RA for gains, RS for losses

insensitivity to middle probabilities

Loss aversion

Next

Mental accounting (Thaler)

segregating and integrating gains and losses

 

Single and repeated choices (Kahneman & Lovallo)

isolation errors